P. Bhaskara Vijayakumar
v.
State
(High Court Of Telangana)
Writ Appeal No. 1822 Of 1985 | 24-04-1987
P.A. CHOUDHARY, J.
(1) ORDER :- This is a writ petition of the genre of public interest litigation. While studying Criminology as part of his third year B. L. degree Course, the petitioner one day on 16th February, 1985 visited the Central Jail at Visakhapatnam. There he noticed the conditions of prisoners in the matter of their working for the prison authorities without getting almost any payment in return. He found the prison authorities extracting work from the prisoners undergoing rigorous imprisonment without paying wages at all or paying nominal wages. He concluded that the prisoners convicted of rigorous imprisonment are thus being exploited and are being subjected to forced labour. Moved by his humane heart which was grieved by the conditions of the prisoners, he filed this writ petition seeking relief of an appropriate writ from this Court under Art. 226 of the Constitution compelling authorities to pay prisoners wages for their work.
(2) I commend the public spirit and endeavour of the petitioner who has not yet ceased to weep over others sorrows and sufferings. The glow of his early thought did not decline in feelings dull decay. His efforts in the interests of those locked up behind the high and not easily accessible walls and almost forgotten and uncared minority of our society is praiseworthy. I, therefore, entertain this writ petition overruling the traditional objection raised by the Advocate General to the maintainability of this writ petition on the round that the petitioner is not an aggrieved person and, therefore, has no locus standi to maintain this Writ Petition. I add to say that in public law unlike in private law many more are welcomed and accepted as aggrieved persons.
(3) THE petitioners case is that extraction of work by the State from the prisoners convicted of rigorous imprisonment without paying for such work is contrary to the mandate of Art. 23 of the Constitution of India which has forbidden the practice of forced labour in our Republic. The petitioner argues that even those prisoners convicted to hard labour are entitled to be paid for the work done by them one extracted from them. He says non-payment to rigorous convicts amounts to State violating Art. 23 of the Constitution. It needs no elaborate argument to show that the State cannot act contrary to or in violation of fundamental rights which are in essence so many limitations on the exercise of State power. It is an established position of the Constitution that State powers are a collection of legal powers and they cannot be exercised contrary to the Constitution. It is equally accepted that the prisoners too are entitled to the enjoyment of such of those fundamental rights enumerated in Part III of our Constitution provided the enjoyment of those rights is not inconsistent with their legal and physical condition of imprisonment to which they have been reduced by reason of their conviction. A prisoner may not enjoy, for example, the right to move throughout the territory of India but he may practice his religion while being a prisoner. The well known judgement of the Supreme Court in State of Maharashtra v. Prabhakar Panduranga AIR 1966 SC 424 [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] ">AIR 1966 SC 424 [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] upheld the right of a prisoner to send his manuscript of a scientific book out of the jail for publication. That judgement is based on facts that firstly there is no law prohibiting a prisoner from publishing a book. Secondly nor such an activity is inconsistent with his detention. Payment of wages to a rigorous imprisoned convict is not forbidden either directly or indirectly by any law. Nor such payment is inconsistent with the legal condition of the convicted prisoner. Both can co-exist. But the question is whether Art. 23 of the Constitution can form the basis for the assertion that a prisoner has a right to be paid wages. (The word wages is used not in scientific sense but in its common sense.) I find the answer to that question in the negative. Art. 23 of the Constitution forbids trafficking in human beings and practice of begar and similar forms of forced labour. The legal consequence of this constitutional injunction is that a human being should not be treated as a commodity or a chattel. Article 23 is a constitutional attempt to establish human dignity. Law cannot recognise or tolerate the institution of forced labour. The question is whether extraction of work without payment from the prisoners can be called pradtice of forced labour within the meaning of Art. 23 and can be compared to trafficking in human beings and begar. I am not inclined to hold that extraction of work from prisoners convicted to hard labour by courts can be regarded as a form of forced labour similar to trafficking in human beings and begar and condemn the institution of hard labour on that ground. Judicial verdict imposes hard labour more as a punishment of the prisoner and less as a means of extraction of useful work from the prisoner. Our first Prime Minister who has spent so many years of his life in jail some of them with hard labour in his autobiography quotes a rule of U. P. Jail Manual to show this real purpose of imposition of rigorous imprisonment. The essence of rigorous imprisonment as established by our penal system is to condemn the prisoner to inconvenience and unpleasantness. Forced labour in Art. 23 connotes employment of labour productively and not as punishment but without the consent of the labourer. If extracting prison work is held to be contrary to Art. 23 on the assumption that it is forced labour a major part of our prison punishment should immediately collapse. In that event, even payment of wages by the State to a prisoner compelled to render such work would not be able to save such an unconstitutional practice because payment of wages alone could not alter the forced character of the labour extracted from the prisoner. The element of compulsion that is present in forcible extraction of labour from the convicted prisoner could not be removed by the mere payment of wages. In fact, such payment cannot be called payment of wages. Wage system of capitalism is normally incompatible with the system of labour forcibly extracted. Such wage system is based on the theoretical freedom of the worker to reject employment. To be a free labourer, the worker should have the choice either to engage himself in the work offered or to refuse to engage himself in that particular work. Lord Atkins famous dictum in Nokes v. Doncaster Amalgamaged Collieries Ltd. 1940 A. C. 104 highlights this aspect of the contract of employment peculiar to capitalism. A prisoner undergoing rigorous imprisonment imposed by a competent judicial organ of the State is by definition denied such liberty even under capitalism either to enter or not to enter a contract of employment. Accepting that extraction of work from a prisoner amounts to extraction of forced labour leads to condemnation of the system of our rigorous imprisonment. It will collapse under the injunction of Art. 23. It is not argued before me that the system of rigorous imprisonment is unconstitutional. Without rigorous imprisonment being held unconstitutional, the concept of forced labour in Art. 23 cannot be held to apply to prison labour. Cruel and unusual punishment except extraction of work as a part of punishment cannot, therefore, be objected to. It must, therefore, be accepted that forced labour is different from labour extracted as punishment. It is for this reason that the XIII amendment to the American Constitution excepts by way of abundant caution punishment imposed for crimes from the category of involuntary servitude and that even Art. 8 of the covenant on human rights declares that any work required to be done in the ordinary course of prison routine by a person undergoing detention imposed by the lawful order of a court should not be considered as forced or compulsory labour. It is difficult to believe that Art. 23 of the Constitution is designed to do away silently and stealthily with these well-known and well-established systems of punishment involved in imposition of rigorous imprisonment and recognised by the civilised world. Otherwise, a major part of our Indian Penal Code has to be declared invalid. There is not enough of textual or historical support either in the language of Art. 23 of the Constitution or its antecedents to justify a holding that imposition of rigorous imprisonment is unconstitutional.
(4) BUT what then is the true scope of Article 23 of the Constitution In answering that question, we should note that Article 23 is in passive voice and does not reveal who the subject is. What is significant is the declaration contained in Art. 23 that contravention of the prohibition contained therein against forced labour or trafficking in human beings is made into an offence. An offence is a commission of crime, not merely acting ultravires. An offence could not normally be envisaged by a nations Constitution to be committed by the State. For these textual reasons, I am of the opinion that Art. 23 is not intended by the Constitution to be a fundamental right directly available against the State. Relevant historical evidence also strengthens this conclusion. The cornerstone of our nation, which our Constitution undoubtedly is, is laid for the erection of a liberal, democratic, egalitarian welfare State But it must be remembered that the Indian State is erected on the un cleared debris of a feudal social order. As our chequered political and social history failed to ensure the growth of indigenous institutions appropriate for a modern liberal State, the task of sweeping away the medieval social and political remnants of inequality and inhumanity and erecting in their place a modern, liberal and egalitarian State is assumed by the Constitution itself. Many of our fundamental rights attempt to remove those remnants of feudal order. This constitutional scavengery of modernising our social order is performed mostly by our fundamental rights like Arts. 17 and 23. Article 17 which abolishes un touchability is not in the main a limitation on the power of the State power as an admonition to the society. So is Art. 23. These Articles belong to a category of fundamental rights which the Germans call Dritwirkung der Grundrechte. Under these constitutional provisions the State is put under a constitutional obligation to refuse recognition and enforcement to the rights arising out of such obnoxious feudal transactions and to provide remedies to the affected individuals for the redressal of violation of his rights by other private individuals. Such rights do not envisage possibility of their violation by the State. This, in my opinion, is the true scope of Art. 23. Thus understood Art. 23 should be held to be more a prohibition directed against the social practices of one member of the society against another rather than a prohibition against the State. I am, therefore, of the opinion that the concept of forced labour in Art. 23 has nothing to do with the protection against the direct action of the State.
(5) THE language of sub-clause (2) of Art. 23 does not in my view militate against the above reasoning. The sub-clause (2) of Art. 23 no doubt says that Art. 23 (1) shall not be understood as preventing the State from imposing compulsory service for public purposes. Thereby the sub-clause might give rise to an impression that the prohibition contained in the main Art. 23 (1) possibly applies to State action also. But on a close look it appears to me that sub-clause (2) is enacted more by way of abundant caution and should also be understood as an independent provision. Imposing compulsory service for public purpose cannot be considered as trafficking in human beings or begar. That is the incidence of citizenship. The justification for enacting sub-clause (2) to Art. 23 has to be found in the anxiety of the Constitution to foreclose a possible argument that such an incidence of citizenship may also fall under the prohibited category of the forced labour.
(6) A prisoner in serving out his sentence and performing hard labour attached to his sentence of rigorous imprisonment cannot be said to be doing any service for any public purpose.
(7) FOR the above reasons, I hold that imposition of rigorous imprisonment with hard labour attached to it does not amount to extracting forced labour from the prisoner and it is not contrary to Art. 23 of the Constitution. I am in full agreement with the American Constitutional rule referred to by Warren, C. J. in Estes v. Texas 14 Led 2d 543 at pages 562, 563 that, "for the Constitution to have vitality, this Court must be able to apply its principles to situations that may not have been foreseen at the time those principles were adopted. . . . . . . . . . Its general principles would have little value and be converted by precedent into impotent and lifeless formulas. Rights declared in words might be lost in reality. " my reason for not adopting that invigorating Americal principle of Constitution to this case is one of principle as I attempted to explain in this judgement. To the above extent I respectfully disagree with the observations made by the Division Bench of the Kerala High Court. In the Matter of P. R. E. of Wages of Prisoners AIR 1983 Ker 267 on which the petitioner placed his entire reliance.
(8) FROM the above it does not follow that this Writ Petition should be dismissed. I am of the opinion that the claim for payment for the work done by the prisoners can be sustained without straining of the constitutional text under Art. 21 of the Constitution. Article 21 of the Constitution guarantees to all persons life and personal liberty against deprivation otherwise than in accordance with the procedure established by law, and is today regarded by the Indian Constitution as one of the most important provisions of the fundamental rights. A prisoner does not cease to be a person merely because he is a prisoner : a prisoner may not enjoy his right to full life and personal liberty guaranteed in Art. 21 because his imprisonment has subtracted a portion of that right. But to the extent that enjoyment of the guaranteed right of Art. 21 is not inconsistent with his condition of imprisonment, a prisoner is still entitled to the protection of Art. 21 of the Constitution. Law no longer is based upon the theory that a convicted person suffers from all public and private legal disabilities. The liberal trend of the modern law of prisons is stated by Halsburys Laws of England IV Edition Volume 37, at paragraph 1137 in these words, "a sentence of imprisonment does not automatically extinguish a prisoners legal rights. " In Paragraph 1138 of the same Volume, it is said, "the ordinary civil and criminal law operates in prisons. . . . . . . . . . In spite of his imprisonment, a convicted prisoner retains all civil rights which are not taken away expressly or by necessary implication. " In this context, we should note the constitutional fact that the words "life and personal liberty" in Art. 21 are vast in their scope and rich and pregnant in their meaning and are sweeping and residuary in their application. The Supreme Court in Olga Tellis case AIR 1986 SC 180 laid it down that the right under Art. 21 comprehends the right to earn ones livelihood. A person because he is in prison does not lose this right so long as his right under Art. 21 can be exercised by him consistently with his imprisonment. Work is necessary for the preservation of life. In England, therefore, a prisoner is not only entitled but he is also bound to work and he is paid for his work at the rates apporved by the Secretary of State. The right of the prisoner to earn his livelihood and to preserve his life thus imposes a corresponding obligation on the State to provide work to the prisoner and pay for it. Such right of the prisoner can only be taken away by a valid law enacted by the legislature, and found by the constitutinal courts to be fair and reasonable. That is the ratio of the two hall-mark decisions of the Supreme Court in Mithus case AIR 1983 SC 473 [LQ/SC/1983/102] and Panduranga Prabhakars case (AIR 1966 SC 424 [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] ">AIR 1966 SC 424 [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] ) (supra) as there is no law enacted by the legislature authorising the State to deny the payment for the work extracted from prisoner, the State would be violating Art. 21 in extracting work from the prisoner without payment.
(9) SECTION 53 of the Indian Penal Code, no doubt, says that offenders are liable for imprisonment of two descriptions namely rigorous imprisonment with hard labour and simple imprisonment without hard labour buy neither Indian Penal Code nor any other law goes further and authorises the State to extract hard labour from the prisoner without payment for the work done by the prisoner. In the absence of such enacted law, it must be held by the courts that the failure of the State to pay for the work extracted from the prisoner amounts to violation of the prisoners right to earn his livelihood. This reasoning cannot be found fault with on the basis that imprisonment will then become the best form of getting employed. Where the State keeps the prisoner in its custody, the above implication becomes unavoidable.
(10) IN the general realm of reason too, one can find no support for the view that the State can deny payment to the prisoners work or that the State is under no obligation to provide any work to the prisoner. Idleness, particularly forced idleness, is sure to destroy a mans life and personal liberty. Contending that a sentence of imprisonment does not cancel an individuals basic human rights to work and to receive payment at the customary rate, the department of Economic and Social Affairs of the United Nations and expressing conscienece of humanity is advocating a far-reaching proposal to integrate prison labour with the free economy of such a nature as to allow, among other things, paying employed prisoners at the going outside rates. A glance at History shows that this is no novel suggestion. Prisoners in Massachusettes (U. S. A.) were being paid for their labour at least from the year 1700 under the laws of that State. Similar legal provisions have been in vogue in other States of the U. S. A. at least from the latter part of the 18th century. Hans V. Hentig writing in Volume 50, Harvard Law Review at page 714 observed : "if we want to keep the prisoner safely, if we want to protect society now and later on, we have to give the convict some outlet for his craving for activity. There is only one decisive aspect to prison labor : the public aspect. . . . . . . . . . . . . There is no "productive labor without some product for the laboring man himself. The prisoners family must be supported or society is charged with an additional burden. " the purpose of imposition of hard labour is not for this purpose of State making profit out of sweat and toil of the prisoner. It is mostly imposed by the statute as a mode of punishment. Paying for the work which the Constitution requires under Art. 21 would not be inconsistent with the purpose behind the imposition of rigorous imprisonment. On the other hand, such payment would benefit the dependents of the prisoner and would help the prisoner to rehabilitate himself with dignity and social utility. It will work out much cheaper for the State to pay the prisoners decently and rehabilitate them to he maximum extent possible than render hem socially useless on their release and burdensome to the community. Supporting the system of payment to the prisoners. Taft and England in their Criminology, Fourth Edition wrote that "wage payment allegedly creates friendly attitudes, develops the feeling that one is a useful worker, and permits the accumulation of savings for the future. " Barnes and Teeters in their New Horizons in Criminology, Third Edition, wrote, "ideally the man in prison should receive a wage so that a part of his compensation could be used to help support his family". The present day object of punishment is mostly preventive and reformative. It is no longer retributive. Moses law of eye for an eye and tooth for a tooth is clearly antiquated. I, therefore, hold that the prisoners would be entitled under Art. 21 of the Constitution to be paid for their labour and the State would be violating the prisoners right to life and personal liberty by extracting labour from them without payment. The present payments being made by the State are awfully inadequate. In them there is neither consideration for their work nor compassion for their fate. I accordingly direct the State of Andhra Pradesh to pay the prisoners adequately for the labour extracted from them.
(11) THE more difficult question then remains is at what rates the prisoners should be paid. The learned Advocate General said that the State is paying at rates which I find to be very nominal. I find the Maharashtra State has also introduced the system of payment to the prisoners. The Kerala High Court held in the above decision (AIR 1983 Ker 261 [LQ/KerHC/1983/118] ) (supra) that the prisoners should be paid on the analogy of free labour. There is ample support for this view in some text-books. But before accepting that view and adopting it as a rule of the Court I think it necessary to get the matter examined in greater detail. However, I am inclined to say that the present rates of wages being paid to the prisoners are awfully inadequate. Considering the fact that the labour is extracted from prisoners partly as a punishment and the Constitution requires the State to provide work for the prisoners and pay for it and rehabilitate them, I am inclined to hold that this matter cannot be decided in this Writ Petition straightway. I think this complex matter requires a further and deeper study by a group of competent penologists, sociologists and economists. I, therefore, direct the State Government to constitute such a committee to consider the various aspects and fix a scale of wages payable to the prisoners which would be fair and considerate to them and would not be unfair to the rest of the society.
(12) IN the terms indicated above, this Writ Petition is allowed. No costs. Petition allowed.
(1) ORDER :- This is a writ petition of the genre of public interest litigation. While studying Criminology as part of his third year B. L. degree Course, the petitioner one day on 16th February, 1985 visited the Central Jail at Visakhapatnam. There he noticed the conditions of prisoners in the matter of their working for the prison authorities without getting almost any payment in return. He found the prison authorities extracting work from the prisoners undergoing rigorous imprisonment without paying wages at all or paying nominal wages. He concluded that the prisoners convicted of rigorous imprisonment are thus being exploited and are being subjected to forced labour. Moved by his humane heart which was grieved by the conditions of the prisoners, he filed this writ petition seeking relief of an appropriate writ from this Court under Art. 226 of the Constitution compelling authorities to pay prisoners wages for their work.
(2) I commend the public spirit and endeavour of the petitioner who has not yet ceased to weep over others sorrows and sufferings. The glow of his early thought did not decline in feelings dull decay. His efforts in the interests of those locked up behind the high and not easily accessible walls and almost forgotten and uncared minority of our society is praiseworthy. I, therefore, entertain this writ petition overruling the traditional objection raised by the Advocate General to the maintainability of this writ petition on the round that the petitioner is not an aggrieved person and, therefore, has no locus standi to maintain this Writ Petition. I add to say that in public law unlike in private law many more are welcomed and accepted as aggrieved persons.
(3) THE petitioners case is that extraction of work by the State from the prisoners convicted of rigorous imprisonment without paying for such work is contrary to the mandate of Art. 23 of the Constitution of India which has forbidden the practice of forced labour in our Republic. The petitioner argues that even those prisoners convicted to hard labour are entitled to be paid for the work done by them one extracted from them. He says non-payment to rigorous convicts amounts to State violating Art. 23 of the Constitution. It needs no elaborate argument to show that the State cannot act contrary to or in violation of fundamental rights which are in essence so many limitations on the exercise of State power. It is an established position of the Constitution that State powers are a collection of legal powers and they cannot be exercised contrary to the Constitution. It is equally accepted that the prisoners too are entitled to the enjoyment of such of those fundamental rights enumerated in Part III of our Constitution provided the enjoyment of those rights is not inconsistent with their legal and physical condition of imprisonment to which they have been reduced by reason of their conviction. A prisoner may not enjoy, for example, the right to move throughout the territory of India but he may practice his religion while being a prisoner. The well known judgement of the Supreme Court in State of Maharashtra v. Prabhakar Panduranga AIR 1966 SC 424 [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] ">AIR 1966 SC 424 [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] upheld the right of a prisoner to send his manuscript of a scientific book out of the jail for publication. That judgement is based on facts that firstly there is no law prohibiting a prisoner from publishing a book. Secondly nor such an activity is inconsistent with his detention. Payment of wages to a rigorous imprisoned convict is not forbidden either directly or indirectly by any law. Nor such payment is inconsistent with the legal condition of the convicted prisoner. Both can co-exist. But the question is whether Art. 23 of the Constitution can form the basis for the assertion that a prisoner has a right to be paid wages. (The word wages is used not in scientific sense but in its common sense.) I find the answer to that question in the negative. Art. 23 of the Constitution forbids trafficking in human beings and practice of begar and similar forms of forced labour. The legal consequence of this constitutional injunction is that a human being should not be treated as a commodity or a chattel. Article 23 is a constitutional attempt to establish human dignity. Law cannot recognise or tolerate the institution of forced labour. The question is whether extraction of work without payment from the prisoners can be called pradtice of forced labour within the meaning of Art. 23 and can be compared to trafficking in human beings and begar. I am not inclined to hold that extraction of work from prisoners convicted to hard labour by courts can be regarded as a form of forced labour similar to trafficking in human beings and begar and condemn the institution of hard labour on that ground. Judicial verdict imposes hard labour more as a punishment of the prisoner and less as a means of extraction of useful work from the prisoner. Our first Prime Minister who has spent so many years of his life in jail some of them with hard labour in his autobiography quotes a rule of U. P. Jail Manual to show this real purpose of imposition of rigorous imprisonment. The essence of rigorous imprisonment as established by our penal system is to condemn the prisoner to inconvenience and unpleasantness. Forced labour in Art. 23 connotes employment of labour productively and not as punishment but without the consent of the labourer. If extracting prison work is held to be contrary to Art. 23 on the assumption that it is forced labour a major part of our prison punishment should immediately collapse. In that event, even payment of wages by the State to a prisoner compelled to render such work would not be able to save such an unconstitutional practice because payment of wages alone could not alter the forced character of the labour extracted from the prisoner. The element of compulsion that is present in forcible extraction of labour from the convicted prisoner could not be removed by the mere payment of wages. In fact, such payment cannot be called payment of wages. Wage system of capitalism is normally incompatible with the system of labour forcibly extracted. Such wage system is based on the theoretical freedom of the worker to reject employment. To be a free labourer, the worker should have the choice either to engage himself in the work offered or to refuse to engage himself in that particular work. Lord Atkins famous dictum in Nokes v. Doncaster Amalgamaged Collieries Ltd. 1940 A. C. 104 highlights this aspect of the contract of employment peculiar to capitalism. A prisoner undergoing rigorous imprisonment imposed by a competent judicial organ of the State is by definition denied such liberty even under capitalism either to enter or not to enter a contract of employment. Accepting that extraction of work from a prisoner amounts to extraction of forced labour leads to condemnation of the system of our rigorous imprisonment. It will collapse under the injunction of Art. 23. It is not argued before me that the system of rigorous imprisonment is unconstitutional. Without rigorous imprisonment being held unconstitutional, the concept of forced labour in Art. 23 cannot be held to apply to prison labour. Cruel and unusual punishment except extraction of work as a part of punishment cannot, therefore, be objected to. It must, therefore, be accepted that forced labour is different from labour extracted as punishment. It is for this reason that the XIII amendment to the American Constitution excepts by way of abundant caution punishment imposed for crimes from the category of involuntary servitude and that even Art. 8 of the covenant on human rights declares that any work required to be done in the ordinary course of prison routine by a person undergoing detention imposed by the lawful order of a court should not be considered as forced or compulsory labour. It is difficult to believe that Art. 23 of the Constitution is designed to do away silently and stealthily with these well-known and well-established systems of punishment involved in imposition of rigorous imprisonment and recognised by the civilised world. Otherwise, a major part of our Indian Penal Code has to be declared invalid. There is not enough of textual or historical support either in the language of Art. 23 of the Constitution or its antecedents to justify a holding that imposition of rigorous imprisonment is unconstitutional.
(4) BUT what then is the true scope of Article 23 of the Constitution In answering that question, we should note that Article 23 is in passive voice and does not reveal who the subject is. What is significant is the declaration contained in Art. 23 that contravention of the prohibition contained therein against forced labour or trafficking in human beings is made into an offence. An offence is a commission of crime, not merely acting ultravires. An offence could not normally be envisaged by a nations Constitution to be committed by the State. For these textual reasons, I am of the opinion that Art. 23 is not intended by the Constitution to be a fundamental right directly available against the State. Relevant historical evidence also strengthens this conclusion. The cornerstone of our nation, which our Constitution undoubtedly is, is laid for the erection of a liberal, democratic, egalitarian welfare State But it must be remembered that the Indian State is erected on the un cleared debris of a feudal social order. As our chequered political and social history failed to ensure the growth of indigenous institutions appropriate for a modern liberal State, the task of sweeping away the medieval social and political remnants of inequality and inhumanity and erecting in their place a modern, liberal and egalitarian State is assumed by the Constitution itself. Many of our fundamental rights attempt to remove those remnants of feudal order. This constitutional scavengery of modernising our social order is performed mostly by our fundamental rights like Arts. 17 and 23. Article 17 which abolishes un touchability is not in the main a limitation on the power of the State power as an admonition to the society. So is Art. 23. These Articles belong to a category of fundamental rights which the Germans call Dritwirkung der Grundrechte. Under these constitutional provisions the State is put under a constitutional obligation to refuse recognition and enforcement to the rights arising out of such obnoxious feudal transactions and to provide remedies to the affected individuals for the redressal of violation of his rights by other private individuals. Such rights do not envisage possibility of their violation by the State. This, in my opinion, is the true scope of Art. 23. Thus understood Art. 23 should be held to be more a prohibition directed against the social practices of one member of the society against another rather than a prohibition against the State. I am, therefore, of the opinion that the concept of forced labour in Art. 23 has nothing to do with the protection against the direct action of the State.
(5) THE language of sub-clause (2) of Art. 23 does not in my view militate against the above reasoning. The sub-clause (2) of Art. 23 no doubt says that Art. 23 (1) shall not be understood as preventing the State from imposing compulsory service for public purposes. Thereby the sub-clause might give rise to an impression that the prohibition contained in the main Art. 23 (1) possibly applies to State action also. But on a close look it appears to me that sub-clause (2) is enacted more by way of abundant caution and should also be understood as an independent provision. Imposing compulsory service for public purpose cannot be considered as trafficking in human beings or begar. That is the incidence of citizenship. The justification for enacting sub-clause (2) to Art. 23 has to be found in the anxiety of the Constitution to foreclose a possible argument that such an incidence of citizenship may also fall under the prohibited category of the forced labour.
(6) A prisoner in serving out his sentence and performing hard labour attached to his sentence of rigorous imprisonment cannot be said to be doing any service for any public purpose.
(7) FOR the above reasons, I hold that imposition of rigorous imprisonment with hard labour attached to it does not amount to extracting forced labour from the prisoner and it is not contrary to Art. 23 of the Constitution. I am in full agreement with the American Constitutional rule referred to by Warren, C. J. in Estes v. Texas 14 Led 2d 543 at pages 562, 563 that, "for the Constitution to have vitality, this Court must be able to apply its principles to situations that may not have been foreseen at the time those principles were adopted. . . . . . . . . . Its general principles would have little value and be converted by precedent into impotent and lifeless formulas. Rights declared in words might be lost in reality. " my reason for not adopting that invigorating Americal principle of Constitution to this case is one of principle as I attempted to explain in this judgement. To the above extent I respectfully disagree with the observations made by the Division Bench of the Kerala High Court. In the Matter of P. R. E. of Wages of Prisoners AIR 1983 Ker 267 on which the petitioner placed his entire reliance.
(8) FROM the above it does not follow that this Writ Petition should be dismissed. I am of the opinion that the claim for payment for the work done by the prisoners can be sustained without straining of the constitutional text under Art. 21 of the Constitution. Article 21 of the Constitution guarantees to all persons life and personal liberty against deprivation otherwise than in accordance with the procedure established by law, and is today regarded by the Indian Constitution as one of the most important provisions of the fundamental rights. A prisoner does not cease to be a person merely because he is a prisoner : a prisoner may not enjoy his right to full life and personal liberty guaranteed in Art. 21 because his imprisonment has subtracted a portion of that right. But to the extent that enjoyment of the guaranteed right of Art. 21 is not inconsistent with his condition of imprisonment, a prisoner is still entitled to the protection of Art. 21 of the Constitution. Law no longer is based upon the theory that a convicted person suffers from all public and private legal disabilities. The liberal trend of the modern law of prisons is stated by Halsburys Laws of England IV Edition Volume 37, at paragraph 1137 in these words, "a sentence of imprisonment does not automatically extinguish a prisoners legal rights. " In Paragraph 1138 of the same Volume, it is said, "the ordinary civil and criminal law operates in prisons. . . . . . . . . . In spite of his imprisonment, a convicted prisoner retains all civil rights which are not taken away expressly or by necessary implication. " In this context, we should note the constitutional fact that the words "life and personal liberty" in Art. 21 are vast in their scope and rich and pregnant in their meaning and are sweeping and residuary in their application. The Supreme Court in Olga Tellis case AIR 1986 SC 180 laid it down that the right under Art. 21 comprehends the right to earn ones livelihood. A person because he is in prison does not lose this right so long as his right under Art. 21 can be exercised by him consistently with his imprisonment. Work is necessary for the preservation of life. In England, therefore, a prisoner is not only entitled but he is also bound to work and he is paid for his work at the rates apporved by the Secretary of State. The right of the prisoner to earn his livelihood and to preserve his life thus imposes a corresponding obligation on the State to provide work to the prisoner and pay for it. Such right of the prisoner can only be taken away by a valid law enacted by the legislature, and found by the constitutinal courts to be fair and reasonable. That is the ratio of the two hall-mark decisions of the Supreme Court in Mithus case AIR 1983 SC 473 [LQ/SC/1983/102] and Panduranga Prabhakars case (AIR 1966 SC 424 [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] ">AIR 1966 SC 424 [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] [LQ/SC/1965/218 ;] ) (supra) as there is no law enacted by the legislature authorising the State to deny the payment for the work extracted from prisoner, the State would be violating Art. 21 in extracting work from the prisoner without payment.
(9) SECTION 53 of the Indian Penal Code, no doubt, says that offenders are liable for imprisonment of two descriptions namely rigorous imprisonment with hard labour and simple imprisonment without hard labour buy neither Indian Penal Code nor any other law goes further and authorises the State to extract hard labour from the prisoner without payment for the work done by the prisoner. In the absence of such enacted law, it must be held by the courts that the failure of the State to pay for the work extracted from the prisoner amounts to violation of the prisoners right to earn his livelihood. This reasoning cannot be found fault with on the basis that imprisonment will then become the best form of getting employed. Where the State keeps the prisoner in its custody, the above implication becomes unavoidable.
(10) IN the general realm of reason too, one can find no support for the view that the State can deny payment to the prisoners work or that the State is under no obligation to provide any work to the prisoner. Idleness, particularly forced idleness, is sure to destroy a mans life and personal liberty. Contending that a sentence of imprisonment does not cancel an individuals basic human rights to work and to receive payment at the customary rate, the department of Economic and Social Affairs of the United Nations and expressing conscienece of humanity is advocating a far-reaching proposal to integrate prison labour with the free economy of such a nature as to allow, among other things, paying employed prisoners at the going outside rates. A glance at History shows that this is no novel suggestion. Prisoners in Massachusettes (U. S. A.) were being paid for their labour at least from the year 1700 under the laws of that State. Similar legal provisions have been in vogue in other States of the U. S. A. at least from the latter part of the 18th century. Hans V. Hentig writing in Volume 50, Harvard Law Review at page 714 observed : "if we want to keep the prisoner safely, if we want to protect society now and later on, we have to give the convict some outlet for his craving for activity. There is only one decisive aspect to prison labor : the public aspect. . . . . . . . . . . . . There is no "productive labor without some product for the laboring man himself. The prisoners family must be supported or society is charged with an additional burden. " the purpose of imposition of hard labour is not for this purpose of State making profit out of sweat and toil of the prisoner. It is mostly imposed by the statute as a mode of punishment. Paying for the work which the Constitution requires under Art. 21 would not be inconsistent with the purpose behind the imposition of rigorous imprisonment. On the other hand, such payment would benefit the dependents of the prisoner and would help the prisoner to rehabilitate himself with dignity and social utility. It will work out much cheaper for the State to pay the prisoners decently and rehabilitate them to he maximum extent possible than render hem socially useless on their release and burdensome to the community. Supporting the system of payment to the prisoners. Taft and England in their Criminology, Fourth Edition wrote that "wage payment allegedly creates friendly attitudes, develops the feeling that one is a useful worker, and permits the accumulation of savings for the future. " Barnes and Teeters in their New Horizons in Criminology, Third Edition, wrote, "ideally the man in prison should receive a wage so that a part of his compensation could be used to help support his family". The present day object of punishment is mostly preventive and reformative. It is no longer retributive. Moses law of eye for an eye and tooth for a tooth is clearly antiquated. I, therefore, hold that the prisoners would be entitled under Art. 21 of the Constitution to be paid for their labour and the State would be violating the prisoners right to life and personal liberty by extracting labour from them without payment. The present payments being made by the State are awfully inadequate. In them there is neither consideration for their work nor compassion for their fate. I accordingly direct the State of Andhra Pradesh to pay the prisoners adequately for the labour extracted from them.
(11) THE more difficult question then remains is at what rates the prisoners should be paid. The learned Advocate General said that the State is paying at rates which I find to be very nominal. I find the Maharashtra State has also introduced the system of payment to the prisoners. The Kerala High Court held in the above decision (AIR 1983 Ker 261 [LQ/KerHC/1983/118] ) (supra) that the prisoners should be paid on the analogy of free labour. There is ample support for this view in some text-books. But before accepting that view and adopting it as a rule of the Court I think it necessary to get the matter examined in greater detail. However, I am inclined to say that the present rates of wages being paid to the prisoners are awfully inadequate. Considering the fact that the labour is extracted from prisoners partly as a punishment and the Constitution requires the State to provide work for the prisoners and pay for it and rehabilitate them, I am inclined to hold that this matter cannot be decided in this Writ Petition straightway. I think this complex matter requires a further and deeper study by a group of competent penologists, sociologists and economists. I, therefore, direct the State Government to constitute such a committee to consider the various aspects and fix a scale of wages payable to the prisoners which would be fair and considerate to them and would not be unfair to the rest of the society.
(12) IN the terms indicated above, this Writ Petition is allowed. No costs. Petition allowed.
Advocates List
For the Appearing Parties ---------------
For Petitioner
- Shekhar Naphade
- Mahesh Agrawal
- Tarun Dua
For Respondent
- S. Vani
- B. Sunita Rao
- Sushil Kumar Pathak
Bench List
HON'BLE MR. JUSTICE P.A. CHOUDHARY
Eq Citation
1987 (2) APLJ (HC) 441
1989 (1) ALT 477
AIR 1988 AP 295
LQ/TelHC/1987/190
HeadNote
Prisoners — Right to Wages — Payment of wages for labour extracted from prisoners — Held, held to be violative of the prisoners’ right to life and personal liberty under Art. 21 — Directed the State Govt. to pay the prisoners adequately for labour extracted from them — Also directed the State Govt. to constitute a committee to consider the various aspects and fix a scale of wages payable to the prisoners which would be fair and considerate to them and would not be unfair to the rest of the society — Indian Penal Code, 1860, S. 53\nArticle 21 & 23, Constitution of India\n
Thank you for subscribing! Please check your inbox to opt-in.
Oh no, error happened! Please check the email address and/or try again.